Theory AdvancedInd
theory AdvancedInd imports Main begin
text‹\noindent
Now that we have learned about rules and logic, we take another look at the
finer points of induction. We consider two questions: what to do if the
proposition to be proved is not directly amenable to induction
(\S\ref{sec:ind-var-in-prems}), and how to utilize (\S\ref{sec:complete-ind})
and even derive (\S\ref{sec:derive-ind}) new induction schemas. We conclude
with an extended example of induction (\S\ref{sec:CTL-revisited}).
›
subsection‹Massaging the Proposition›
text‹\label{sec:ind-var-in-prems}
Often we have assumed that the theorem to be proved is already in a form
that is amenable to induction, but sometimes it isn't.
Here is an example.
Since \<^term>‹hd› and \<^term>‹last› return the first and last element of a
non-empty list, this lemma looks easy to prove:
›
lemma "xs ≠ [] ⟹ hd(rev xs) = last xs"
apply(induct_tac xs)
txt‹\noindent
But induction produces the warning
\begin{quote}\tt
Induction variable occurs also among premises!
\end{quote}
and leads to the base case
@{subgoals[display,indent=0,goals_limit=1]}
Simplification reduces the base case to this:
\begin{isabelle}
\ 1.\ xs\ {\isasymnoteq}\ []\ {\isasymLongrightarrow}\ hd\ []\ =\ last\ []
\end{isabelle}
We cannot prove this equality because we do not know what \<^term>‹hd› and
\<^term>‹last› return when applied to \<^term>‹[]›.
We should not have ignored the warning. Because the induction
formula is only the conclusion, induction does not affect the occurrence of \<^term>‹xs› in the premises.
Thus the case that should have been trivial
becomes unprovable. Fortunately, the solution is easy:\footnote{A similar
heuristic applies to rule inductions; see \S\ref{sec:rtc}.}
\begin{quote}
\emph{Pull all occurrences of the induction variable into the conclusion
using ‹⟶›.}
\end{quote}
Thus we should state the lemma as an ordinary
implication~(‹⟶›), letting
\attrdx{rule_format} (\S\ref{sec:forward}) convert the
result to the usual ‹⟹› form:
›
oops
lemma hd_rev [rule_format]: "xs ≠ [] ⟶ hd(rev xs) = last xs"
apply(induct_tac xs)
txt‹\noindent
This time, induction leaves us with a trivial base case:
@{subgoals[display,indent=0,goals_limit=1]}
And ‹auto› completes the proof.
If there are multiple premises $A@1$, \dots, $A@n$ containing the
induction variable, you should turn the conclusion $C$ into
\[ A@1 \longrightarrow \cdots A@n \longrightarrow C. \]
Additionally, you may also have to universally quantify some other variables,
which can yield a fairly complex conclusion. However, ‹rule_format›
can remove any number of occurrences of ‹∀› and
‹⟶›.
\index{induction!on a term}%
A second reason why your proposition may not be amenable to induction is that
you want to induct on a complex term, rather than a variable. In
general, induction on a term~$t$ requires rephrasing the conclusion~$C$
as
\begin{equation}\label{eqn:ind-over-term}
\forall y@1 \dots y@n.~ x = t \longrightarrow C.
\end{equation}
where $y@1 \dots y@n$ are the free variables in $t$ and $x$ is a new variable.
Now you can perform induction on~$x$. An example appears in
\S\ref{sec:complete-ind} below.
The very same problem may occur in connection with rule induction. Remember
that it requires a premise of the form $(x@1,\dots,x@k) \in R$, where $R$ is
some inductively defined set and the $x@i$ are variables. If instead we have
a premise $t \in R$, where $t$ is not just an $n$-tuple of variables, we
replace it with $(x@1,\dots,x@k) \in R$, and rephrase the conclusion $C$ as
\[ \forall y@1 \dots y@n.~ (x@1,\dots,x@k) = t \longrightarrow C. \]
For an example see \S\ref{sec:CTL-revisited} below.
Of course, all premises that share free variables with $t$ need to be pulled into
the conclusion as well, under the ‹∀›, again using ‹⟶› as shown above.
Readers who are puzzled by the form of statement
(\ref{eqn:ind-over-term}) above should remember that the
transformation is only performed to permit induction. Once induction
has been applied, the statement can be transformed back into something quite
intuitive. For example, applying wellfounded induction on $x$ (w.r.t.\
$\prec$) to (\ref{eqn:ind-over-term}) and transforming the result a
little leads to the goal
\[ \bigwedge\overline{y}.\
\forall \overline{z}.\ t\,\overline{z} \prec t\,\overline{y}\ \longrightarrow\ C\,\overline{z}
\ \Longrightarrow\ C\,\overline{y} \]
where $\overline{y}$ stands for $y@1 \dots y@n$ and the dependence of $t$ and
$C$ on the free variables of $t$ has been made explicit.
Unfortunately, this induction schema cannot be expressed as a
single theorem because it depends on the number of free variables in $t$ ---
the notation $\overline{y}$ is merely an informal device.
›
by auto
subsection‹Beyond Structural and Recursion Induction›
text‹\label{sec:complete-ind}
So far, inductive proofs were by structural induction for
primitive recursive functions and recursion induction for total recursive
functions. But sometimes structural induction is awkward and there is no
recursive function that could furnish a more appropriate
induction schema. In such cases a general-purpose induction schema can
be helpful. We show how to apply such induction schemas by an example.
Structural induction on \<^typ>‹nat› is
usually known as mathematical induction. There is also \textbf{complete}
\index{induction!complete}%
induction, where you prove $P(n)$ under the assumption that $P(m)$
holds for all $m<n$. In Isabelle, this is the theorem \tdx{nat_less_induct}:
@{thm[display]"nat_less_induct"[no_vars]}
As an application, we prove a property of the following
function:
›
axiomatization f :: "nat ⇒ nat"
where f_ax: "f(f(n)) < f(Suc(n))" for n :: nat
text‹
\begin{warn}
We discourage the use of axioms because of the danger of
inconsistencies. Axiom ‹f_ax› does
not introduce an inconsistency because, for example, the identity function
satisfies it. Axioms can be useful in exploratory developments, say when
you assume some well-known theorems so that you can quickly demonstrate some
point about methodology. If your example turns into a substantial proof
development, you should replace axioms by theorems.
\end{warn}\noindent
The axiom for \<^term>‹f› implies \<^prop>‹n <= f n›, which can
be proved by induction on \mbox{\<^term>‹f n›}. Following the recipe outlined
above, we have to phrase the proposition as follows to allow induction:
›
lemma f_incr_lem: "∀i. k = f i ⟶ i ≤ f i"
txt‹\noindent
To perform induction on \<^term>‹k› using @{thm[source]nat_less_induct}, we use
the same general induction method as for recursion induction (see
\S\ref{sec:fun-induction}):
›
apply(induct_tac k rule: nat_less_induct)
txt‹\noindent
We get the following proof state:
@{subgoals[display,indent=0,margin=65]}
After stripping the ‹∀i›, the proof continues with a case
distinction on \<^term>‹i›. The case \<^prop>‹i = (0::nat)› is trivial and we focus on
the other case:
›
apply(rule allI)
apply(case_tac i)
apply(simp)
txt‹
@{subgoals[display,indent=0]}
›
by(blast intro!: f_ax Suc_leI intro: le_less_trans)
text‹\noindent
If you find the last step puzzling, here are the two lemmas it employs:
\begin{isabelle}
@{thm Suc_leI[no_vars]}
\rulename{Suc_leI}\isanewline
@{thm le_less_trans[no_vars]}
\rulename{le_less_trans}
\end{isabelle}
%
The proof goes like this (writing \<^term>‹j› instead of \<^typ>‹nat›).
Since \<^prop>‹i = Suc j› it suffices to show
\hbox{\<^prop>‹j < f(Suc j)›},
by @{thm[source]Suc_leI}\@. This is
proved as follows. From @{thm[source]f_ax} we have \<^prop>‹f (f j) < f (Suc j)›
(1) which implies \<^prop>‹f j <= f (f j)› by the induction hypothesis.
Using (1) once more we obtain \<^prop>‹f j < f(Suc j)› (2) by the transitivity
rule @{thm[source]le_less_trans}.
Using the induction hypothesis once more we obtain \<^prop>‹j <= f j›
which, together with (2) yields \<^prop>‹j < f (Suc j)› (again by
@{thm[source]le_less_trans}).
This last step shows both the power and the danger of automatic proofs. They
will usually not tell you how the proof goes, because it can be hard to
translate the internal proof into a human-readable format. Automatic
proofs are easy to write but hard to read and understand.
The desired result, \<^prop>‹i <= f i›, follows from @{thm[source]f_incr_lem}:
›
lemmas f_incr = f_incr_lem[rule_format, OF refl]
text‹\noindent
The final @{thm[source]refl} gets rid of the premise ‹?k = f ?i›.
We could have included this derivation in the original statement of the lemma:
›
lemma f_incr[rule_format, OF refl]: "∀i. k = f i ⟶ i ≤ f i"
oops
text‹
\begin{exercise}
From the axiom and lemma for \<^term>‹f›, show that \<^term>‹f› is the
identity function.
\end{exercise}
Method \methdx{induct_tac} can be applied with any rule $r$
whose conclusion is of the form ${?}P~?x@1 \dots ?x@n$, in which case the
format is
\begin{quote}
\isacommand{apply}‹(induct_tac› $y@1 \dots y@n$ ‹rule:› $r$‹)›
\end{quote}
where $y@1, \dots, y@n$ are variables in the conclusion of the first subgoal.
A further useful induction rule is @{thm[source]length_induct},
induction on the length of a list\indexbold{*length_induct}
@{thm[display]length_induct[no_vars]}
which is a special case of @{thm[source]measure_induct}
@{thm[display]measure_induct[no_vars]}
where \<^term>‹f› may be any function into type \<^typ>‹nat›.
›
subsection‹Derivation of New Induction Schemas›
text‹\label{sec:derive-ind}
\index{induction!deriving new schemas}%
Induction schemas are ordinary theorems and you can derive new ones
whenever you wish. This section shows you how, using the example
of @{thm[source]nat_less_induct}. Assume we only have structural induction
available for \<^typ>‹nat› and want to derive complete induction. We
must generalize the statement as shown:
›
lemma induct_lem: "(⋀n::nat. ∀m<n. P m ⟹ P n) ⟹ ∀m<n. P m"
apply(induct_tac n)
txt‹\noindent
The base case is vacuously true. For the induction step (\<^prop>‹m <
Suc n›) we distinguish two cases: case \<^prop>‹m < n› is true by induction
hypothesis and case \<^prop>‹m = n› follows from the assumption, again using
the induction hypothesis:
›
apply(blast)
by(blast elim: less_SucE)
text‹\noindent
The elimination rule @{thm[source]less_SucE} expresses the case distinction:
@{thm[display]"less_SucE"[no_vars]}
Now it is straightforward to derive the original version of
@{thm[source]nat_less_induct} by manipulating the conclusion of the above
lemma: instantiate \<^term>‹n› by \<^term>‹Suc n› and \<^term>‹m› by \<^term>‹n›
and remove the trivial condition \<^prop>‹n < Suc n›. Fortunately, this
happens automatically when we add the lemma as a new premise to the
desired goal:
›
theorem nat_less_induct: "(⋀n::nat. ∀m<n. P m ⟹ P n) ⟹ P n"
by(insert induct_lem, blast)
text‹
HOL already provides the mother of
all inductions, well-founded induction (see \S\ref{sec:Well-founded}). For
example theorem @{thm[source]nat_less_induct} is
a special case of @{thm[source]wf_induct} where \<^term>‹r› is ‹<› on
\<^typ>‹nat›. The details can be found in theory \isa{Wellfounded_Recursion}.
›
end